One
of the things I have learned about blogging is that it is not a place for long
tirades. People get bored and don’t want to spend their time reading you work
out your issues in the digital domain. I know first hand, because I have rambled
about stuff that gets the universal “what the hell are you talking about?”
response. My readership numbers directly correlate to these posts. Talk a
little, and they go up. Talk a lot, and they go down. So this little number should
send the numbers right through the floor.
Everyone
is blogging and talking about the Adler and Sumser conflict. I think that’s a
good thing. But the debate seems mostly uninformed by corporate history, sound business theory or
any basic understanding of the legal issues involved. So I thought I would
reflect a little bit on these topics.
First,
the entire discussion starts on the premise of the permanence of the labor
contract. All arguments that have been posted start with an assumption about
the level of hold an employer has on their employees. Many have related this to
slavery: you haven’t been able to “own” a person since the emancipation
proclamation (or Lee’s surrender at Appomattox),
and so every employee is a free agent, completely free of the bonds of
corporate servitude. Then there are those that say that approaching an employee
of another company is like “stealing” – the person is (supposedly) happily
employed and you go in there and try to poach / steal / take them out of that
environment, which has does material harm to the company being alleviated of
their employee.
Corporate History
In
pre-industrial society (after feudalism but before mass production) you started
as an apprentice. Fathers sold their sons into the employ of an artisan or
craftsman so that the boy could learn their trade, eventually graduating out of
apprenticeship to full artisan or craftsman status. It was against the law to
try to “poach” someone out of this situation. (Many people still are stuck with
this notion – that while you are getting your bread and education from someone
else you are “owned” by them and that it would be bad practice to try to lure
them away from a situation to which they are ethically and legally committed.)
Two
things happened to change this: the civil war and the development of the steam
engine. Steam power moved industrial production from craftsmanship to mass
production, so people became employed by a large enterprise, not by an
individual. Most people understand that. But what they don’t understand is that
the very nature of the industrial enterprise was changed by the civil war.
Companies no longer had to get congressional approval for incorporation. Lincoln needed more
corporations to supply his troops, so congress changed the rules to make it
easier to set up (and disband) a corporation. In other words, when the
corporation became impermanent (since the barrier to entry and penalty for exit
were both reduced), so did the employment contract.
This
(and not the Japanese miracle of the 70’s) was the start of our “free agent” work place. Over time the contractual
obligation between the employer and
employee has gotten weaker and weaker. You knew that “ownership” of an employee
was dead as a concept when IBM had its first layoffs in the 80’s. But this
doesn’t mean that an employee has no obligation to the employer. Quite the
contrary. In fact, the obligation of an employee to hold a employer’s
information as valuable and proprietary information is at the heart of the rest
of our analysis.
But
overall the basic premise that recruiters “steal” employees is fundamentally
bankrupt, not because slavery is dead, but because free market economics has
successfully killed off every form of employee indenture, starting with feudalism,
working through apprenticeship, and ending with life-long employment contracts.
Employees are free agents in as much as they can freely change employment at
will. And while the fluidity of the employment contract may cause real harm to
employers as an employee who is critical to some part of the business is able
to leave freely and without bondage, the value to individual to freely pursue their
interests (perhaps this is the real “pursuit of happiness” of which Jefferson
spoke?) outweighs the potential damage to the corporation.
Therefore
it is not stealing or poaching (or whatever derogatory name you want to hang on
the practice) when you attempt to recruit someone from another company, even if
they are a competitor and by virtue of your act of recruiting you are impairing
the competitor’s ability to compete in the marketplace.
So
if engaging in the act of recruiting from another company is both legal and
ethical (as defined by a civilly and legally defensible act that does not
markedly decrease the value of your brand in the marketplace), then you have
not crossed the line into hell whereby all actions are justified because you
have already decided to do bad things (the old “if you are going to hold up a
liquor store you might as well murder the clerk” argument of ethics, which is
one of two roots of all evil, but I digress).
Business Theory and
Practice
Sound
business theory says that your objective is to create value for your investors.
You must provide a greater rate of return than they would get for a similar
amount of risk out of another enterprise. Therefore there are some enterprises
which may provide a lot of return to investors, but with a high degree of risk,
and others that the opposite (low return, low risk).
Engaging
in risky business practice may be justified by the return. Many (most)
businesses engage in behavior that according to a personal code of ethics would
be abhorrent but which in a business are expected (“vapor ware” in the software
industry is a great example).
Business
seeks to return value to shareholders within a very constrained value system:
“value for value” and “reward exceeds risk.” Over time government (as an agency
of the people) has constrained business behavior: what is good for GM is not
always good for America.
They do this by proscribing criminal controls (fraud is a criminal activity for
instance) and civil law controls (failing to file you annual corporate meetings
minutes for instance) as a consequence for behavior that is seen an
antithetical to the good of the society as a whole.
These
consequences are risks, and therefore must be taken into account in the “reward
exceeds risk” calculation. After all, if your company is going to get fined for
undertaking a certain activity then that is a risk that may outweigh the value
of the anticipated reward for executing that activity.
Again,
businesses are not operating in the ethical constraints that an individual is.
The corporation does not seek to get into heaven, and doesn’t have to look
itself in the mirror in the morning. (I personally disagree with the basic
corporate structure – it was wrong for the East India Company and its wrong
today, but that is another question for another day.) But businesses do have to
assess whether their activities create risks for their shareholders that outweigh
the probability of return from pulling it off.
Legal Issues
So
rather than focusing on the ethical questions of this debate, focus on the
business issues. And the business issues are pretty significant. If you, as an
individual or agent of a company, intentionally use deception as a method of
business, you are more than likely liable for a civil action. Your risk
equation has to include the probability that you will be caught and the
probability that you will be sued. In the past, in the “wink-and-a-nod”
underworld of recruiting, these probabilities were calculated to be low, so lying
and deception were common practice. As the risk of these activities increases
we will seeing a corresponding decrease in their use.
However,
if you use deception as a method of getting an individual to break their
contractual obligation to another person, thereby exposing the person who is
deceived to civil action themselves, you are more than likely guilty of fraud.
That is a criminal activity. As an example, if you employ the tactic of rusing
someone into giving a name, and the person you ruse is under a standard
employment contract, then you have encouraged them to break their contractual
agreement with their employer that they will hold such information in
confidence. If that person gets fired for such an activity, it is clear they
have a civil action available to them (they can sue you), and it may be that
the enterprise can report you to the DA for your activity.
Again,
there is no need to view this from an ethical framework. This is just risk /
reward analysis. The risk is real. How likely are you to be caught, and if
caught sued and / or prosecuted? Only you can evaluate that. But given the fact
that most recruiters are not trained in business theory and risk calculations,
it is likely that their calculations are wrong. In other words, you are
probably taking on a lot more risk than you think you are.
But
what is the reward? If the reward for success is greater than the penalty for
failure then it may be worth doing (assuming you have evaluated the probabilities
of both occurrences correctly). It may be possible that the big score is worth
the possible suit, or even going to jail. But only if the probability of
getting the big score is substantially increased by the behavior in question.
And
in this case, the answer is clearly “no.” A person who lies and engages in
subterfuge in order to obtain the names of candidates is not significantly more
successful in their efforts than a person who does not engage in such behavior.
They may be marginally more successful, but the reward is clearly not worth the
extra risk, even if you assume that the risk is negligible (and I can claim
with certainty that the risk is both significant and growing by virtue of this
debate coming to light).
I
think Heather Hamilton’s article got to the basis of this, as has much good
commentary. I do applaud ERE for publishing both sides of this debate, and for
bringing it to forefront. In fact, from the “sound business theory”
perspective, ERE has reduced the risk of my company by showing me the people
who would in fact increase my risk of doing business by employing lying and
subterfuge as business methods. This has been a real value to the larger (and
therefore more exposed) companies that read the ERE articles and watch the
dialogue on the boards.
You're the man, Jeff! Once again, you said something that I wish I said (but wouldn't be able to if I sat in front a stack of industrial theory and history books for a few years).
Posted by: Heather | October 06, 2005 at 10:12 AM